Thursday, November 8, 2018

thaw philosophy


Thaw philosophy
Comparative philosophy built on and from differences


1.     Philosophy is not about the world but embodies and condenses it.
2.     Those condensations are concepts and their constellations.
3.     A concept captures a certain singularity in embodied interaction in the world.
4.     Philosophical thinking as creating and managing concepts does thus not take place in a separate realm but moves inside this world itself.
5.     A concept is different from an abstraction. The latter is formed by discarding individual and particular variations, retaining an empty shell of their form. A “horse”: a mere linguistic habit. A concept, instead, situates itself in an articulation of the world itself, in the articulation of interaction of the things and events of the world, in their mutual affections (affecting and being affected) and capacities. It does not discard anything of the variability, but on the contrary corresponds to a singularity of the world that is actualized in certain variations.
6.     Concepts form constellations where they mutually throw light on or reflect each other in a kind of Indra’s net. In this way they condense each other. A concept primarily has meaning through this constellation; separated from it, its meaning remains undetermined. This is different from scientific terms, where c has a specific reference on its own: the velocity of light in vacuum. But we cannot say what is in a Confucian philosophy, without taking into account also what is 義、樂、禮、忠、恕 etc. Even if we separately analyze philosophically one of those terms, this takes place on the background of those other concepts that throw light on it.
7.     Philosophical concepts and their constellations are also different from opinions that operate in the mode of habits and abstractions. Even if some opinions may correspond to a real articulation of the world, they perform mechanically and in this way can easily become inadequate, unadaptive and out of date. Like a spider might react when you by hand vibrate its net, and come to search for food, because usually this vibration is a sign of a prey struggling in spider’s net. Thus, an opinion does not really concern the articulations of neither the world nor the person. We may have strong attachments to certain opinions that we defend fiercely, but which may still not express what we really are in our articulation of singularities. We have simply taken our opinions from others, interiorized them, and conform to them.
8.     A concept is formed like the “common notions” in Deleuze’s interpretation of Spinoza. A common notion (a “second” type of knowledge) is not an abstraction ( “first” type, lower type of knowledge). It is not formed “top down” (a “horse” that is superposed to particular horses), but “bottom up”. For example, learning to swim means that I match the singularities of my body to the singularities of the water. Usually this doesn’t happen all at once but requires some experimentation, trying. In the same way I learn to “match” my body and mind to lots of different things, persons, environments. And in this way a common notion loses nothing of the variability. On the contrary, it lives on them, and adapts to them. I can not only swim at my uncle’s place in a river in Estonia, but also in Xiamen University’s water reservoir. It is not tied to the metric properties of the counterpart, but to its singularities, to its articulation or . Or to take Merleau-Ponty’s example: organs, the musical instruments, can be widely different: the number of keys, placement of registers may differ greatly, but still an organist can very quickly adapt to a new organ, because she does not play an example of the abstraction “organ”, but matches her non-metric or intensive articulation to that of the instrument, and can change the metric expression of her movements according to the particular instrument. She doesn’t play a metric thing x centimeters long and y centimeters wide, but a more interpenetrating instrument. Indeed, she does not even play an instrument, but she plays music, and her symbiosis with the organ is just a conduit or locus for the actualization of a musical piece. Singularities denote sensitive regions in the behavior of a system. For instance, a collection of H2O molecules has two singularities, around 0 and around 100 degrees at sea level, where system abruptly changes: ice melts, water evaporates. In the course of heating, there are some linear changes (molecules vibrate more and more), and two abrupt changes (a completely different cohesion between molecules: solid crystals, liquid, gas). And further singularities in the water, for example: when a recipient of water is gradually warmed from the bottom, there are distinct ways it behaves: diffusion of heat (molecules moving faster at the bottom transmitting energy to those above that are moving slower), convection cells (large streams that rotate either clockwise or counterclockwise), turbulence (boiling). This is a very simple example, but human life in the same way has singularities and “regular points” between them. Some of them very imposing, like death, for instance, or other persons, or “self”, etc.
9.     Philosophical concepts work on this kind of singularities or common notions. They do not refer to the metrical and fully actualized world, but to the world in a more interpenetrating phase and express the singular points of it. It means also that one’s body and mind are intimately involved – and again, not one’s fully actualized (and so to say “metric”) body and mind, with its habits and opinions, but body and mind in a more interpenetrating phase, where capacities, tendencies and lines of force express my map of singularities. These singularities of myself and of the world (of things, events, persons, environments) cannot be made explicit directly, because they are what myself am, and I do not have an external fulcrum to perform this. Rather what I can do, is to form a constellation of concepts that as a group would express my being-in-the-world and being-with-others. In a narrowly philosophical sense they are usually embodied in words or expressions, but these words should not be taken as terms of science or as reified opinions. A constellation of concepts of a philosopher testifies to an effort of dismantling or thawing up of bodily, social and linguistic habits, in order to get to the genetic point of things and events, to their interpenetrating phase. Indeed, a philosopher’s thought is actualized in words and works, but one should see the interpenetration and the singularities that gave birth to it. Without this, philosophy appears utterly meaningless, pretentious, oppressive and perhaps even depressive. With this, it becomes joyful, because it is an aid for one’s own difficult process of dismantling, thawing and transforming.
10.  Yet this kind of gradual process of forming common notions and discovering singularities is also misleading. In another sense, philosophy starts from a leap, an absolute deterritorialization, estrangement or “forgetting”. Or with an “intellectual love of God”, as Spinoza termed his third kind of knowledge, that does not build higher and richer common notions, but starts already from the Other, the Groundless, a pure cut in my existence. Not simply a skill (shu ), but a Way (dao ). A turning point: not a counter-actualization from the actual towards the virtual, but a free and easy actualization from the virtual, from the singularities of the world, events, beings, my own form, energy and mind.
11.  Philosopher’s life is not only actualized in philosophical works, of course, but also in her other activities. They express her singularities and intensities. The latter never invalidate the former (because philosophy, in general, cannot be completely invalidated), but they do modify it and perhaps reinterpret it. Take Heidegger’s involvement with Nazi ideology or Sartre’s infidelity. Heidegger still remains one of the most important philosophers of the 20th century, but this involvement does throw a different light on his insistence of German particularity (philosophy can be done only in German and Greek), and also his references to the idyllic countryside life become suspicious (Blut und Boden). But it would be stupid to discard his philosophy for this reason. It simply helps us better to see his reterritorializing tendencies. And Sartre’s (purportedly consensual) infidelity is part of his way of life, from which originate also his philosophical works that stress voluntarism, ungroundedness of existence, etc. And when we denounce a philosopher’s thought on the ground of his or her other activities, we should be clear about the character of our attack: is it simply based on opinion (for instance, a philosopher breaches a social convention); or on concepts (but then we should create concepts for those other activities, like Mozi did for those who support war); or on another constellation of concepts (a most common case of disagreement between philosophers – a question of “taste”, as Nietzsche said –, based on the fact that you embody different singularities and intensities than that other philosopher).
12.  What is the role of comparative philosophy here? We do not create concepts out of thin air, but on the basis of an earlier tradition. Although a philosopher thaws up a world and a heritage, she still scavenges a lot of her material from former buildings. In this way even in philosophy there form certain habits – for instance in focus: what is considered important and what not: Greeks made great effort to incorporate scientific knowledge, but largely discarded the analysis of consciousness. The Indians made elaborate analysis of consciousness but discarded “mundane” relations. The Chinese investigated non-linear interactions between things, persons, environments and came out with a wonderful conception of embodied knowledge. All of these three perhaps disregarded our commonality and continuity with other beings, that was an important topic for so many “indigenous ontologies”, together with the worldview implicated in such a wonderful personage like trickster, creative and dumb at the same time, a cultural hero creating cultural artifacts, and obscene at the same time, etc. Those ontologies may contain things that were wiped under the rug in the more hierarchical, normalized, “civilized”, oedipalized societies. Now, an encounter with another tradition can further help the process of dismantling and thawing, since in different traditions there are differences in focus, emphasis, methods, approaches, and they help to dissipate false self-evidences, thought habits. There are different procedures to put the thought into motion again (one can generate thought on the basis of linguistic similarities or assonances, like Heidegger’s Ereignis as er-eignen etc., or Chinese and ; or one can turn to art, literature, science, nature, etc., like Deleuze’s account of Proust, Francis Bacon, Kafka, film, etc.). But turning to other philosophical traditions is especially important in our day, because it would free the practice of philosophy from some of its colonialist and racist heritage (see Van Norden’s book “Taking back philosophy” for that respect) that encumbers its flowing. Because these days in the whole world the majority of work done under the label of “philosophy” is in reality restricted to the Western philosophy (and now even to just one very small branch of it, the Analytic philosophy). Other traditions are mostly ignored, and it easily brings about an implicit feeling of superiority, of supremacy toward other traditions. Philosophy seems to be the last bastion of colonialism. The West has been defeated or rivalled economically and militarily, but it jealously protects its most internal dungeon, its thought tradition that it tries to present as the only one worth of the name “philosophy” (i.e. the label that we find on the philosophy departments’ doors and in the titles of journals).
13.  Comparative philosophy does not take place on the level of fully actualized forms: in that case there would never be a true comparison in the sense of a transformative communication, but merely a forcing of one into the terms of the other, or simple juxtaposition of “facts”; like in Zhuangzi’s story about the impossibility of judging who is right and who is wrong in a discussion.[1] A true comparison takes place more “upstream” from the actualized forms, on the level of intensities and singularities. It is there that elements from different thought traditions can resonate and compose with each other (and not simple “opinions” to arrange one next to another), giving rise to new becomings. Traditions must first be put in a furnace, so that they melt and become malleable. They must be thawed, so that what is frozen or coagulated (ning ) start to move according to their energy or capacities (qi ), revealing their virtual articulations, their singularities and differential relations (li ). Actual differences between traditions may inflict an initial shock that puts thought into motion; intensive differences enable creative couplings, and virtual differences reconfigure the whole world we live in.


[1] In Zhuangzi 2.12: “Suppose that you and I have a dispute. If you beat me and I lose to you, does that mean you’re really right and I'm really wrong? If I beat you and you lose to me, does that mean I'm really right and you’re really wrong? Is one of us right and the other wrong? Or are both of us right and both of us wrong? Neither you nor I can know, and others are even more in the dark. Whom shall we have decide the matter? Shall we have someone who agrees with you decide it? Since he agrees with you, how can he decide fairly? Shall we have someone who agrees with me decide it? Since he agrees with me, how can he decide fairly? Shall we have someone who differs with both of us decide it? Since he differs with both of us, how can he make a decision? Shall we have someone who agrees with both of us decide it? Since he agrees with both of us, how can he make a decision? Given that neither you nor I, nor another person, can know how to decide, shall we wait for still another?” (Mair 1994: 23). 既使我與若辯矣,若勝我,我不若勝,若果是也?我果非也邪?我勝若,若不吾勝,我果是也?而果非也邪?其或是也,其或非也邪?其俱是也,其俱非也邪?我與若不能相知也,則人固受其黮闇。吾誰使正之?使同乎若者正之,既與若同矣,惡能正之!使同乎我者正之,既同乎我矣,惡能正之!使異乎我與若者正之,既異乎我與若矣,惡能正之!使同乎我與若者正之,既同乎我與若矣,惡能正之!然則我與若與人俱不能相知也,而待彼也邪?

No comments:

Post a Comment