Sunday, September 29, 2019

matterialism and spiritwoalism2

(The first part of the text figures also in a previous post)
 
Matterialism and spiritwoalism

The orthography “matterialism” is meant to stress that, first, it is not a question of materialism as opposed to spiritualism, a reduction of first-person experience and interactions with second persons to third-person events, e.g. my experience of myself and of my relation to my friend as reduced to certain events in my nervous system, especially brain, and to some other physical, chemical and biological events, e.g. that my friend is a material object from which visual, acoustic and tactile impulses reach my body, are registered and transferred to the brain as a CPU that would process that physico-chemical information, and produce a certain output, e.g. certain behavior towards my friend (for instance, we shake hands, I register a usual friendly expression on his face, and I try to produce also a friendly expression, and perhaps utter some accompanying words, like “To have friends arrive from afar—is this not a joy?”). Second, it is not about matter as opposed to form, a passive material substance upon which a certain form is impressed like an amphora is made of clay.
Instead, matterialism is about materials as having their inherent articulations, tendencies and capacities. And it does not reduce the first- and second-person experience to third-person givens: materials themselves have a certain self-relation, and certain ways of interacting with others as well. A material can be taken in an extremely broad sense: not only substances like wood or iron or water or air, but also the whole environment and any being or thing in it may be treated as the material for the present action. The whole context of my activity is a material for it.
The orthography of “spiritwoalism” is also meant to capture certain ideas that keep it distinct from another notion, spiritualism. First, it is not a denial or suppression of matter or materials; on the contrary, it finds its expression only through certain materials, and with their help. Second, spirit is often considered as something unitary, undifferentiated, identical with itself. The “two” in the term “spiritwoalism” stresses the fact that my consciousness of myself is inseparable from my consciousness of some other (person, thing, event, environment). It applies not only to humans, but can be stated generally: a self-relation is necessarily also an other-relation. The “two” does not indicate that the participants have to be necessarily two and only two, but the relation between two is meant to be taken as a synecdoche (“part for the whole”) for any relation “between”, and the focus should be on the betweenness rather than on the actualized terms between which it takes place. The “two” also refers to the matterialism as a counterpart of a spiritwoalism.
A matterialism naturally unfolds itself into a spiritwoalism, and spiritwoalism is always also a matterialism.


Multitude

One important philosophical consequence of matterialism and spiritwoalism is the ontological role of the multitude. The multitude is an independent ontological category, it is not just an aggregate of „monads“ (Leibniz) or „primary beings“ (Ruyer). When things are generated in the Big Bang, it is not a “Big Bang begets one, one begets two, two begets three” (to paraphrase Laozi §42), but there is right away a multitude, a pullulation of larval entities. And all major leaps in complexity (including the birth of life or of humans) take place in a multitude, a “primordial soup”, a society. Although the societies in which humans evolved may have been a handful of bands of a couple of dozen individuals, the society represents a distinct level of organization and behavior.
In a multitude there are emergent behaviors that can not be reduced to a single individual or even a pair of them. It is in a multitude that matter (physical, chemical, biological, social) displays its singularities. For example, a multitude of H2O molecules display two singularities, one phase transition between solid and liquid and another between liquid and gaseous around 0 and 100 degrees Celsius at sea level on Earth. Furthermore, its liquid state, water, displays distinct modes of internal movement: heat transmission, convection cells, turbulence. These singularities emerge from a multitude, in a context where a multitude of entities or processes constrain each other; where their interactions start to flow in some veins that characterizes a new kind of entity or process.
Raymond Ruyer distinguished between primary and secondary beings1 so that primary beings are characterized by a true form that they they "surview" (survol) and to some extent maintain (electron, proton, atom, molecule, cell, living being); and secondary beings are simply aggregates of primary beings and their form is simply a result of contiguity-interactions (de proche en proche) and statistical rules (soap bubble, planet, society viewed through statistics, etc.). They have no form of their own, but their form is produced simply by the activities of primary beings that it contains - the resultant behavior may well have regularities and constants, but ontologically it would all be derivative, based on and resulting from the primary beings and their activities.
Manuel DeLanda, with a Deleuzian inspiration, gives much higher ontological status to the multitudes - that are not simply individual entities, nor simple statistical outcomes. It is not simply individual with interiority, nor an external aggregate.
It would be a misconception to reduce the multitude (or all multitudes) to the interactions of "primary beings". The singularities of a multitude are embodied by that multitude itself. We may perhaps concede to Ruyer and say with him that, for example, an electron, a proton, an atom, a molecul, a cell, a human are all in the same line as rather strongly individuated entities, but it does not mean that the more complex entities or processes would grow out of the more simple ones, that they would be kind of "extensions" of the simpler ones; the descriptive similarity does not entail any genetic similarity. The complex structures are always formed from a multitude: a quark-gluon plasma, primordial soup of organic matter, etc. Although the interactions between ruyerian primary beings are important for the complexification as the proximate or effective cause, but they do not explain it; it is explained by veins of a multitude, by the constraints that emerge in a multitude, as a distal or formal cause. What those veins do is to distribute the energy of being in a more nuanced, differentiated way, and in higher temporal and spatial scales. So that, in a Deaconian sense, a new kind of work can be done.


Intensities

The matterial interactions are intensive, both in the colloquial sense of energetic (versus merely contemplative, indifferent), and in the technical sense of involving intensive properties of things and the body. Intensive properties are those that cannot be divided in a simple manner like extensive properties2: for instance, if you divide a certain volume of water of a certain temperature into half, you get two volumes half the previous size (extensive property), but of the same temperature (intensive property). Initially the whole interaction with materials: with things, beings and environments is intensive, and stable persisting identities are only gradually attributed to them (and simultaneously a more stable sense of self is formed), to which quantitative and metric properties can be attributed. This tendency is carried to the end at school, where in the lessons of mathematics and physics all things are learnt to be homogenized and treated in quantitative and metric terms; and at the same time a more distanced and external stance is taken also to one's own body and subjectivity: one learns that one's body is made up of the same substances and elements as other things, and in the lessons of anatomy one studies the layout of body as a juxtaposition of organs and tissues, as a „res extensa“, extended thing with extensive properties.
Whereas intensive is thus dragged towards the actual and juxtaposing - and for some purposes it is useful, so that it can be subjected to mathematical calculations -, it should correspondingly be taken (why not also at school?) further also from the other end, towards „more“ interpenetrating, towards the virtual differential relations and singularities from which the intensities are developed and unfolded. How can this be done?
This can be performed by another, different effort of thinking. There are larval subjects in all of the intensities. For example, the intensive property of temperature (or pressure) in the water results from the collisions between water molecules; but a water molecule is an entity that manages to maintain its form (two hydrogen atoms around the oxigen atom) and that enters into contact with other water molecules (especially via hydrogen bonds, that add to the bonds between a single oxigen and hydrogens, making the connectivity inside the water stronger). It surviews its form and offers a certain resistance to attempts to change it: and that is the reason why changes on the microscopic level are never continuous, but quantic: a larval subject has contracted space-time in a certain form and by this very contraction maintains it, even if in very short spatial and temporal scale (but not smaller than the order of Planck units). This manifests the first forms of self-relation.
Those entities are not self-enclosed, but always interact with some others: already with itself as an other in the sense that they endure, which means that they re-create themselves, tending to the next moment and over some space: their being is not punctual and momentaneous, but they contract some space-time, which means that they are already also elsewhere, elsetimes, and hence something else. Being a self always also enails being other-than-self. There is a cut inside every being that simultaneously creates a certain space-time, a contraction of points and moments, and also by the same act transcends it to other spaces and times. This is the foundation of our common space and time.
And by the same act, the entity is towards other entities, so that a self-relation is intrinsically also other-relation. There cannot be a self without an other, or a consciousness without a subconscious; the most primordial about these things being the very cut that separates them. From this separation, from a multitude a new kind of system may emerge, with its own veins or constraints and its own energy or work that it is able to extract.
Entities/processes can form assemblies, like quark-processes in a nucleon or nucleon-processes in a nucleus or electron- and nucleus-processes in an atom, atom-processes in a molecule or molecule-processes (chemical reactions) in a cell. They can form more or less individuated assemblies: a ball, a stone, a river, a dog, a human.


Self-cultivation. Common notions

Materials surround us always. Already in the womb we explore our surroundings. Even in the very beginning, as a fertilized egg, we use certain materials in order to build our body. And when we are born, we gradually start to explore the world we are in. We feel mother and other persons and perhaps animals, occasionally we encounter parts of our own body, when we agitate our hands and they pass our visual field, of when they touch each other, we learn to grab things and bring them to the mouth, we taste, touch, watch, listen them. They present a certain texture and structure, certain affordances (where to grab); they react to our behavior in a certain way, they let themselves be affected by us in a certain way, and affect us back in a certain way. In a sense, a child is already a scientist, actively manipulating the things in her surroundings in order to observe their reactions.
There is the material of things or stuff; then there is the material of the environment like ground or air; and there is the material that exhibits sponatneity like other people, animals, insects, also plants (in slower time-scales). The distinction between beings and things is initially not clear, since inanimate things also may behave unexpectedly and they exhibit a resistance and their own articulations and logic that is never completely under my dominion, and it is not so unjustified if a child says that „the table hit me“. The table, by being in a position to encounter child's body, and by presenting its resistance to it, in a sense also „behaves“. Animism, according to which any thing may be reanimated, has its justification.
We explore what is outside, and simultaneously train our body and mind. Together with a more nuanced understanding of things, materials, beings, environments, we obtain a more nuanced command of our body. A toy with which the child plays, works in both directions, it reveals further articulations and capacities of itself, and at the same time it brings out articulations and capacities of the body that plays with it. With the growing experience of materials and its own body, the child starts to form virtual models of the reality. This capacity is enhanced by the acquisition of language, that then becomes yet another material for exploration for the child.
So, dealing with materials and environments is already a self-cultivation. A material, has its own consistency or internal energy and veins, it manifests a certain opposition, presents surprises, has its own articulations, its own ways of affecting and being affected. Materials lure us, challenge us, force us out of a simple being-in-ourselves. In the process of interaction with materials we learn how to proceed, how to behave, how to move, where to direct our attention etc. We learn how our body and mind fits (or does not fit) the material. In Spinozian terms, we form „common notions“ with it, a "second kind of knowledge", beyond mere chance encounters that are a "first kind of knowledge".
The question is not, how to be „rational“ and free from the deceptions and contingencies of the body. The question is, how to melt up the actualized forms, both bodily and mental, and how to move towards the virtual. The formation of common notions means to learn to interpenetrate with the material, i.e. to form an assamblage with it. When we form more and more common notions, we learn how to interpenetrate with more materials: things, beings, environments, processes, and to do it in more varied conditions. So, in this matterialistic self-cultivation my spirit is in "two", between the two, it is a spiritwoalism.
This brings about a leap, that Spinoza calls third kind of knowledge or an intellectual love of God. It is becoming-equal with the unequal itself, identifying oneself with the Difference, integrating with the Cut that cuts through all identities and integrities. It is a leap from the intensive to the virtual, where all the things, beings, environments etc. perplicate each other. Having one part of it, you have all of it, implicitly. Then in your field of individuation are involved all the other fields of individuation.


Heterotopy, heterochrony, heterosubjectivity. Singular-universal vs particular-general

With complexification, the spatial and temporal scales widen. With humans, it potentially reaches the maximum: we can, in principle, grasp the whole of the universe, i.e. the maximum of heterotopy, as well as the birth and possible end (by heat death, Big Crunch or otherwise) of it, i.e. the maximum of heterochrony. We can go to the limit of space and time. We can think of the „whole“ of being (although, of course, it creates a paradox, because this thought should be not contained in that whole, which means that the whole is not a whole, and we would need a new thought to think this greater whole, but again, this thought would not be included in the new whole, and so on to infinity). or, better, our existence takes place on the background of this whole, which we can in a certain sense intend, even if paradoxically or asymptotically.
We can, in principle, also grasp a complete Otherness (religions tend to reterritorialize it into a supreme Being, a God, World Spirit, or other, with dire consequences; this onto-theology is the supreme veneration of a being, making a theology around a being or an idea, thus discarding, suppressing, destroying the Otherness).
From matterialistic spiritwoalism, I can discover the Cut that cuts the maximum of time, space and alterity. I exist in relation to the maximum of other-timeness, other-spaceness and otherness.
By the same token, everything becomes singular. When we come back from this maximum of alterity to the here and now, then these things, beings, persons, environments, materials that we encounter, they acquire an enhanced meaning, they become singular (and not just exemplars of a general type). The least important (taking into consideration the immensity of the universe) can be also the most important (as these singular things here in this unique situation). This does not deny the validity of general notions and ideas, for instance, the scientific formulas and categories, but it includes it into a more comprehensive worldview, into the uniqueness of the situation. General ideas may give us good, reliable and useful hints there, but they are not sufficient, they are not precise enough for philosophical purposes. Beyond the everyday logic of particular and general there is the logic of singular and universal.
Hence, spiritwoalism does not so much aim to destroy religions or spiritualities, as to demythologize them. There are no fixed or predetermined points for self-cultivation or "spiritual excercises", but anything can give material for it. The small arts described in Zhuangzi (carpenter, butcher, cicada-catcher, etc.) give a brilliant example of it. And the self-cultivation proceeds in these cases from the materials and the practitioner's body themselves, from their interaction. It does require some effort, practice, and concentration, but they are not prescribed from outside of the system, and it defyies all pre-established hierarchies. Yet, through this practice, it is possible to somehow get closer to the most external exteriority there is, i.e. to the cut itself, that cuts me from the other, my consciousness from my subconscious, one bodily organization level from another.
1 There's nothing wrong with that distinction; it comes at the very beginning of his book and heuristically it is still a very good starting point. Only that this must be refined later.
2Cf. Wikipedia, where material's properties are said to be intensive in the sense of „a physical property that does not depend on the amount of the material.

No comments:

Post a Comment